4.4 Ordering[27K]
[26H] We will study an order relation \(≤\) on \(ℕ\) (not necessarily total) such that
where as usual
- E146
[267]Suppose that \(≤\) is a (possibly partial) order relation on \(ℕ\) satisfying 143 then \(≤\) is unique. Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’270’]
- E146
[271]Let
\[ P_ x =\{ z∈ ℕ, z{\lt} x\} \]show that
\[ ∀ x,y∈ ℕ~ ,~ P_ x = P_ y ⇒ x=y \]using the properties in Hypothesis 143.
Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’272’]
(Note the similarity with 7).
- E146
[276]By setting \(n=x=y\) in ?? we obtain that \(n{\lt}Sn\).
- E146
[277]Prerequisites:3,143.Using the properties in 143 and assuming that \(≤\) is a total order relation (as will be proven), prove that
\[ ∀ n,m∈ ℕ, (n{\lt} m ) ⇒ (Sn{\lt} Sm)\quad . \]Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’278’]
- E146
[26X]If \(⪯\) is a total order on \(ℕ\) then these are equivalent
\begin{align} ∀ x,y∈ ℕ , & (x⪯ y⪯ Sx ) ⇒ (x=y∨ y=Sx)\quad ,\label{eq:caratt_ le_ N_ mid}\\ ∀ x,y ∈ℕ , & (x≺ Sy) \iff (x ⪯ y ) \quad ; \\ ∀ x,y ∈ℕ , & (x≺ y) \iff (Sx ⪯ y ) \quad . \label{eq:caratt_ le_ N_ alt} \end{align}Note the analogy with 3
Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’296’]
Ordering from arithmetic[287]
Having already defined arithmetic, a convenient definition of ordering is as follows.
[288] Given \(n,m∈ ℕ\), we will say that \(n≤ m\) if there exists \(k∈ℕ\) such that \(n+k=m\)
[289] Let \(n,m,k∈ℕ\).
For every \(n\) we have \(0\le n\)
\(n≤ m\) if and only if \(n{\lt} S(m)\).
Note that these two points satisfy ??,?? in 143
For every \(n\) we have \(n{\lt}S(n)\)
\(n{\lt}m\) if and only if \(S(n)≤ m\).
If \(n≤ m ≤ S(n)\) then \(m=n\) or \(m=S(n)\).
The proofs are left as exercise 1. (After we will prove that the relation is total, then by 5 the last two are equivalent.)
[298]Hence this relation “\(\le \)” defined in 150 satisfies the principle 143; we will show that any such ordering is a well order; here we present though a self contained proof for this specific case.
[28Z] \(≤\) is a total order relation.
Consider the proposition
then \(P(0)\) is true. Let’s assume \(P(n)\); let’s fix an \(m\);
if \(m≤ n\) then \(m≤ S(n)\), by the lemma (point 2), so \(P(Sn)\) holds;
if \(¬ m≤ n\) but \(P(n)\) holds, then \(n≤ m\) must hold, but it cannot be \(n=m\), so \(n{\lt}m\) holds: but then \(S(n)≤ m\) by the lemma (point 4);
in any case \(P(S(n))\) is proven starting from \(P(n)\).
[297] \(≤\) is a well ordering.
- E155
[28D] Show properties in 151. Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’28F’]
- E155
[28G]Show that if \(n≤ m\) then \(m-n≤ m\). Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’28H’]
- E155
[28N] Show that if \(n≠ 0\) then \(n× m≥ m\). Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’28P’]
- E155
[28J] Topics:Euclidean division.
Prove that, given \(d,n∈ℕ,d≥ 1\), two numbers \(q,r∈ℕ,0≤ r {\lt} d\) exist and are unique for which \(n=q×d +r\) (where \(n\) is the ”dividend” \(d\) is the ”divisor”, \(q\) is the ”quotient” and \(r\) is the ”remainder”) Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’28K’]
- E155
[28M] (Replaces 282)
Let \(h≠ 0\), prove that if \(n× h= m× h\) then \(n= m\). (Sugg. use subtraction)
Hidden solution: [UNACCESSIBLE UUID ’28S’]
In particular the map \(n\mapsto n× h\) is injective.
Ordering and arithmetic [28Q]
The ordering is compatible with arithmetic.
(Addition and ordering compatibility) You have \(n≤ m\) if and only if \(n+k≤ m+k\).
(Multiplication and ordering compatibility) When \(k≠ 0\) you have \(n≤ m\) if and only if \(n× k≤ m× k\).
In particular (remembering 5) the map \(n\mapsto n× h\) is strictly increasing (and hence injective).
We will use some properties left for exercise.
If \(n≤ m\), by definition \(m=n+h\), then \(n+k≤ m+k\) because \(m+k=n+h+k\) (note that we are using associativity). If \(n+k≤ m+k\) let then \(j\) the only natural number such that \(n+k+j= m+k\) but then \(n+j= m\) by cancellation 3.
If \(n≤ m\) then \(m=n+h\) therefore \(m× k=n× k+h× k\) so \(n× k≤ m× k\). Vice versa let \(k≠ 0\) and \(n× k≤ m× k\) i.e. \(n× k + j= m× k\): divide \(j\) by \(k\) using the division 4, we write \(j=q× k + r\) therefore for associativity \((n+q)× k + r= m× k\) but for the uniqueness of the division \(r=0\); eventually collecting \((n+q)× k = m× k\) and using 5 we conclude that \((n+q) = m\).